text/ncat.tex
changeset 142 16539d77fb37
parent 141 e1d24be683bb
child 143 c46b2a01e789
equal deleted inserted replaced
141:e1d24be683bb 142:16539d77fb37
   254 
   254 
   255 \nn{Almost certainly we need a little more than the above axiom.
   255 \nn{Almost certainly we need a little more than the above axiom.
   256 More specifically, in order to bootstrap our way from the top dimension
   256 More specifically, in order to bootstrap our way from the top dimension
   257 properties of identity morphisms to low dimensions, we need regular products,
   257 properties of identity morphisms to low dimensions, we need regular products,
   258 pinched products and even half-pinched products.
   258 pinched products and even half-pinched products.
   259 I'm not sure what the best way to cleanly axiomatize the properties of these various is.
   259 I'm not sure what the best way to cleanly axiomatize the properties of these various
       
   260 products is.
   260 For the moment, I'll assume that all flavors of the product are at
   261 For the moment, I'll assume that all flavors of the product are at
   261 our disposal, and I'll plan on revising the axioms later.}
   262 our disposal, and I'll plan on revising the axioms later.}
   262 
   263 
   263 \nn{current idea for fixing this: make the above axiom a ``preliminary version"
   264 \nn{current idea for fixing this: make the above axiom a ``preliminary version"
   264 (as we have already done with some of the other axioms), then state the official
   265 (as we have already done with some of the other axioms), then state the official
   299 We define a map
   300 We define a map
   300 \begin{eqnarray*}
   301 \begin{eqnarray*}
   301 	\psi_{Y,J}: \cC(X) &\to& \cC(X) \\
   302 	\psi_{Y,J}: \cC(X) &\to& \cC(X) \\
   302 	a & \mapsto & s_{Y,J}(a \cup ((a|_Y)\times J)) .
   303 	a & \mapsto & s_{Y,J}(a \cup ((a|_Y)\times J)) .
   303 \end{eqnarray*}
   304 \end{eqnarray*}
   304 \nn{need to say something somewhere about pinched boundary convention for products}
   305 (See Figure \ref{glue-collar}.)
       
   306 \begin{figure}[!ht]\begin{equation*}
       
   307 \mathfig{.9}{tempkw/glue-collar}
       
   308 \end{equation*}\caption{Extended homeomorphism.}\label{glue-collar}\end{figure}
   305 We will call $\psi_{Y,J}$ an extended isotopy.
   309 We will call $\psi_{Y,J}$ an extended isotopy.
   306 \nn{or extended homeomorphism?  see below.}
   310 \nn{or extended homeomorphism?  see below.}
   307 \nn{maybe remark that in some examples (e.g.\ ones based on sub cell complexes) 
   311 \nn{maybe remark that in some examples (e.g.\ ones based on sub cell complexes) 
   308 extended isotopies are also plain isotopies, so
   312 extended isotopies are also plain isotopies, so
   309 no extension necessary}
   313 no extension necessary}
   358 
   362 
   359 \medskip
   363 \medskip
   360 
   364 
   361 The alert reader will have already noticed that our definition of (plain) $n$-category
   365 The alert reader will have already noticed that our definition of (plain) $n$-category
   362 is extremely similar to our definition of topological fields.
   366 is extremely similar to our definition of topological fields.
   363 The only difference is that for the $n$-category definition we restrict our attention to balls
   367 The main difference is that for the $n$-category definition we restrict our attention to balls
   364 (and their boundaries), while for fields we consider all manifolds.
   368 (and their boundaries), while for fields we consider all manifolds.
   365 \nn{also: difference at the top dimension; fix this}
   369 (A minor difference is that in the category definition we directly impose isotopy
       
   370 invariance in dimension $n$, while in the fields definition we have non-isotopy-invariant fields
       
   371 but then mod out by local relations which imply isotopy invariance.)
   366 Thus a system of fields determines an $n$-category simply by restricting our attention to
   372 Thus a system of fields determines an $n$-category simply by restricting our attention to
   367 balls.
   373 balls.
   368 The $n$-category can be thought of as the local part of the fields.
   374 This $n$-category can be thought of as the local part of the fields.
   369 Conversely, given an $n$-category we can construct a system of fields via 
   375 Conversely, given an $n$-category we can construct a system of fields via 
   370 \nn{gluing, or a universal construction}
   376 a colimit construction; see below.
   371 \nn{see subsection below}
   377 
   372 
   378 %\nn{Next, say something about $A_\infty$ $n$-categories and ``homological" systems
   373 \nn{Next, say something about $A_\infty$ $n$-categories and ``homological" systems
   379 %of fields.
   374 of fields.
   380 %The universal (colimit) construction becomes our generalized definition of blob homology.
   375 The universal (colimit) construction becomes our generalized definition of blob homology.
   381 %Need to explain how it relates to the old definition.}
   376 Need to explain how it relates to the old definition.}
       
   377 
   382 
   378 \medskip
   383 \medskip
   379 
   384 
   380 \nn{these examples need to be fleshed out a bit more}
   385 \nn{these examples need to be fleshed out a bit more}
   381 
   386 
   403 \nn{need to say something about fundamental classes, or choose $\alpha$ carefully}
   408 \nn{need to say something about fundamental classes, or choose $\alpha$ carefully}
   404 
   409 
   405 \item Given a traditional $n$-category $C$ (with strong duality etc.),
   410 \item Given a traditional $n$-category $C$ (with strong duality etc.),
   406 define $\cC(X)$ (with $\dim(X) < n$) 
   411 define $\cC(X)$ (with $\dim(X) < n$) 
   407 to be the set of all $C$-labeled sub cell complexes of $X$.
   412 to be the set of all $C$-labeled sub cell complexes of $X$.
       
   413 (See Subsection \ref{sec:fields}.)
   408 For $X$ an $n$-ball and $c\in \cC(\bd X)$, define $\cC(X)$ to finite linear
   414 For $X$ an $n$-ball and $c\in \cC(\bd X)$, define $\cC(X)$ to finite linear
   409 combinations of $C$-labeled sub cell complexes of $X$
   415 combinations of $C$-labeled sub cell complexes of $X$
   410 modulo the kernel of the evaluation map.
   416 modulo the kernel of the evaluation map.
   411 Define a product morphism $a\times D$ to be the product of the cell complex of $a$ with $D$,
   417 Define a product morphism $a\times D$ to be the product of the cell complex of $a$ with $D$,
   412 and with the same labeling as $a$.
   418 and with the same labeling as $a$.
   418 \nn{refer elsewhere for details?}
   424 \nn{refer elsewhere for details?}
   419 
   425 
   420 \item Variation on the above examples:
   426 \item Variation on the above examples:
   421 We could allow $F$ to have boundary and specify boundary conditions on $X\times \bd F$,
   427 We could allow $F$ to have boundary and specify boundary conditions on $X\times \bd F$,
   422 for example product boundary conditions or take the union over all boundary conditions.
   428 for example product boundary conditions or take the union over all boundary conditions.
   423 \nn{maybe should not emphasize this case, since it's ``better" in some sense
   429 %\nn{maybe should not emphasize this case, since it's ``better" in some sense
   424 to think of these guys as affording a representation
   430 %to think of these guys as affording a representation
   425 of the $n{+}1$-category associated to $\bd F$.}
   431 %of the $n{+}1$-category associated to $\bd F$.}
   426 
   432 
   427 \item \nn{should add bordism $n$-cat}
   433 \item Here's our version of the bordism $n$-category.
       
   434 For a $k$-ball $X$, $k<n$, define $\cC(X)$ to be the set of all $k$-dimensional
       
   435 submanifolds $W$ of $X\times \r^\infty$ such that the projection $W \to X$ is transverse
       
   436 to $\bd X$.
       
   437 For $k=n$ define $\cC(X)$ to be homeomorphism classes (rel boundary) of such submanifolds;
       
   438 we identify $W$ and $W'$ if $\bd W = \bd W'$ and there is a homeomorphism
       
   439 $W\to W'$ which restricts to the identity on the boundary.
       
   440 
   428 
   441 
   429 \end{itemize}
   442 \end{itemize}
   430 
   443 
   431 
   444 
   432 Examples of $A_\infty$ $n$-categories:
   445 Examples of $A_\infty$ $n$-categories:
   461 (If $k = n$ and our $k$-categories are enriched, then
   474 (If $k = n$ and our $k$-categories are enriched, then
   462 $\cC(W)$ will have additional structure; see below.)
   475 $\cC(W)$ will have additional structure; see below.)
   463 $\cC(W)$ will be the colimit of a functor defined on a category $\cJ(W)$,
   476 $\cC(W)$ will be the colimit of a functor defined on a category $\cJ(W)$,
   464 which we define next.
   477 which we define next.
   465 
   478 
   466 Define a permissible decomposition of $W$ to be a decomposition
   479 Define a permissible decomposition of $W$ to be a cell decomposition
   467 \[
   480 \[
   468 	W = \bigcup_a X_a ,
   481 	W = \bigcup_a X_a ,
   469 \]
   482 \]
   470 where each $X_a$ is a $k$-ball.
   483 where each closed top-dimensional cell $X_a$ is an embedded $k$-ball.
   471 Given permissible decompositions $x$ and $y$, we say that $x$ is a refinement
   484 Given permissible decompositions $x$ and $y$, we say that $x$ is a refinement
   472 of $y$, or write $x \le y$, if each ball of $y$ is a union of balls of $x$.
   485 of $y$, or write $x \le y$, if each ball of $y$ is a union of balls of $x$.
   473 This defines a partial ordering $\cJ(W)$, which we will think of as a category.
   486 This defines a partial ordering $\cJ(W)$, which we will think of as a category.
   474 (The objects of $\cJ(W)$ are permissible decompositions of $W$, and there is a unique
   487 (The objects of $\cJ(W)$ are permissible decompositions of $W$, and there is a unique
   475 morphism from $x$ to $y$ if and only if $x$ is a refinement of $y$.
   488 morphism from $x$ to $y$ if and only if $x$ is a refinement of $y$.
   499 (If $\dim(W) = n$ then we need to also make use of the monoidal
   512 (If $\dim(W) = n$ then we need to also make use of the monoidal
   500 product in the enriching category.
   513 product in the enriching category.
   501 \nn{should probably be more explicit here})
   514 \nn{should probably be more explicit here})
   502 
   515 
   503 Finally, define $\cC(W)$ to be the colimit of $\psi_\cC$.
   516 Finally, define $\cC(W)$ to be the colimit of $\psi_\cC$.
   504 In the plain (non-$A_\infty$) case, this means that
   517 When $k<n$ or $k=n$ and we are in the plain (non-$A_\infty$) case, this means that
   505 for each decomposition $x$ there is a map
   518 for each decomposition $x$ there is a map
   506 $\psi_\cC(x)\to \cC(W)$, these maps are compatible with the refinement maps
   519 $\psi_\cC(x)\to \cC(W)$, these maps are compatible with the refinement maps
   507 above, and $\cC(W)$ is universal with respect to these properties.
   520 above, and $\cC(W)$ is universal with respect to these properties.
   508 In the $A_\infty$ case, it means 
   521 When $k=n$ and we are in the $A_\infty$ case, it means
   509 \nn{.... need to check if there is a def in the literature before writing this down;
   522 homotopy colimit.
   510 homotopy colimit I think}
       
   511 
   523 
   512 More concretely, in the plain case enriched over vector spaces, and with $\dim(W) = n$, we can take
   524 More concretely, in the plain case enriched over vector spaces, and with $\dim(W) = n$, we can take
   513 \[
   525 \[
   514 	\cC(W) = \left( \oplus_x \psi_\cC(x)\right) \big/ K
   526 	\cC(W) = \left( \oplus_x \psi_\cC(x)\right) \big/ K
   515 \]
   527 \]
   517 $a\in \psi_\cC(x)$ for some decomposition $x$, $x\le y$, and $g: \psi_\cC(x)
   529 $a\in \psi_\cC(x)$ for some decomposition $x$, $x\le y$, and $g: \psi_\cC(x)
   518 \to \psi_\cC(y)$ is value of $\psi_\cC$ on the antirefinement $x\to y$.
   530 \to \psi_\cC(y)$ is value of $\psi_\cC$ on the antirefinement $x\to y$.
   519 
   531 
   520 In the $A_\infty$ case enriched over chain complexes, the concrete description of the colimit
   532 In the $A_\infty$ case enriched over chain complexes, the concrete description of the colimit
   521 is as follows.
   533 is as follows.
   522 \nn{should probably rewrite this to be compatible with some standard reference}
   534 %\nn{should probably rewrite this to be compatible with some standard reference}
   523 Define an $m$-sequence to be a sequence $x_0 \le x_1 \le \dots \le x_m$ of permissible decompositions.
   535 Define an $m$-sequence to be a sequence $x_0 \le x_1 \le \dots \le x_m$ of permissible decompositions.
   524 Such sequences (for all $m$) form a simplicial set.
   536 Such sequences (for all $m$) form a simplicial set.
   525 Let
   537 Let
   526 \[
   538 \[
   527 	V = \bigoplus_{(x_i)} \psi_\cC(x_0) ,
   539 	V = \bigoplus_{(x_i)} \psi_\cC(x_0) ,
   807 
   819 
   808 \medskip
   820 \medskip
   809 
   821 
   810 Examples of modules:
   822 Examples of modules:
   811 \begin{itemize}
   823 \begin{itemize}
   812 \item
   824 \item \nn{examples from TQFTs}
       
   825 \item \nn{for maps to $T$, can restrict to subspaces of $T$;}
   813 \end{itemize}
   826 \end{itemize}
   814 
   827 
   815 \subsection{Modules as boundary labels}
   828 \subsection{Modules as boundary labels}
   816 \label{moddecss}
   829 \label{moddecss}
   817 
   830 
   829 	W = (\bigcup_a X_a) \cup (\bigcup_{i,b} M_{ib}) ,
   842 	W = (\bigcup_a X_a) \cup (\bigcup_{i,b} M_{ib}) ,
   830 \]
   843 \]
   831 where each $X_a$ is a plain $k$-ball (disjoint from $\bd W$) and
   844 where each $X_a$ is a plain $k$-ball (disjoint from $\bd W$) and
   832 each $M_{ib}$ is a marked $k$-ball intersecting $\bd_i W$,
   845 each $M_{ib}$ is a marked $k$-ball intersecting $\bd_i W$,
   833 with $M_{ib}\cap\bd_i W$ being the marking.
   846 with $M_{ib}\cap\bd_i W$ being the marking.
       
   847 \nn{need figure}
   834 Given permissible decompositions $x$ and $y$, we say that $x$ is a refinement
   848 Given permissible decompositions $x$ and $y$, we say that $x$ is a refinement
   835 of $y$, or write $x \le y$, if each ball of $y$ is a union of balls of $x$.
   849 of $y$, or write $x \le y$, if each ball of $y$ is a union of balls of $x$.
   836 This defines a partial ordering $\cJ(W)$, which we will think of as a category.
   850 This defines a partial ordering $\cJ(W)$, which we will think of as a category.
   837 (The objects of $\cJ(D)$ are permissible decompositions of $W$, and there is a unique
   851 (The objects of $\cJ(D)$ are permissible decompositions of $W$, and there is a unique
   838 morphism from $x$ to $y$ if and only if $x$ is a refinement of $y$.)
   852 morphism from $x$ to $y$ if and only if $x$ is a refinement of $y$.)