text/ncat.tex
changeset 913 75c1e11d0f25
parent 904 fab3d057beeb
child 914 db365e67adf6
equal deleted inserted replaced
912:c43f9f8fb395 913:75c1e11d0f25
    17 Compared to other definitions in the literature,
    17 Compared to other definitions in the literature,
    18 the definitions presented below tie the categories more closely to the topology
    18 the definitions presented below tie the categories more closely to the topology
    19 and avoid combinatorial questions about, for example, finding a minimal sufficient
    19 and avoid combinatorial questions about, for example, finding a minimal sufficient
    20 collection of generalized associativity axioms; we prefer maximal sets of axioms to minimal sets.
    20 collection of generalized associativity axioms; we prefer maximal sets of axioms to minimal sets.
    21 It is easy to show that examples of topological origin
    21 It is easy to show that examples of topological origin
    22 (e.g.\ categories whose morphisms are maps into spaces or decorated balls, or bordism categories), 
    22 (e.g.\ categories whose morphisms are maps into spaces or decorated balls, or bordism categories)
    23 satisfy our axioms.
    23 satisfy our axioms.
    24 To show that examples of a more purely algebraic origin satisfy our axioms, 
    24 To show that examples of a more purely algebraic origin satisfy our axioms, 
    25 one would typically need the combinatorial
    25 one would typically need the combinatorial
    26 results that we have avoided here.
    26 results that we have avoided here.
    27 
    27 
    40 Axiom \ref{axiom:extended-isotopies} with Axiom \ref{axiom:families}.
    40 Axiom \ref{axiom:extended-isotopies} with Axiom \ref{axiom:families}.
    41 
    41 
    42 Strictly speaking, before we can state the axioms for $k$-morphisms we need all the axioms 
    42 Strictly speaking, before we can state the axioms for $k$-morphisms we need all the axioms 
    43 for $k{-}1$-morphisms.
    43 for $k{-}1$-morphisms.
    44 Readers who prefer things to be presented in a strictly logical order should read this 
    44 Readers who prefer things to be presented in a strictly logical order should read this 
    45 subsection $n+1$ times, first setting $k=0$, then $k=1$, and so on until they reach $k=n$.
    45 subsection $n{+}1$ times, first setting $k=0$, then $k=1$, and so on until they reach $k=n$.
    46 
    46 
    47 \medskip
    47 \medskip
    48 
    48 
    49 There are many existing definitions of $n$-categories, with various intended uses.
    49 There are many existing definitions of $n$-categories, with various intended uses.
    50 In any such definition, there are sets of $k$-morphisms for each $0 \leq k \leq n$.
    50 In any such definition, there are sets of $k$-morphisms for each $0 \leq k \leq n$.
    88 %\nn{need to check whether this makes much difference}
    88 %\nn{need to check whether this makes much difference}
    89 (If smooth, ``homeomorphism" should be read ``diffeomorphism", and we would need
    89 (If smooth, ``homeomorphism" should be read ``diffeomorphism", and we would need
    90 to be fussier about corners and boundaries.)
    90 to be fussier about corners and boundaries.)
    91 For each flavor of manifold there is a corresponding flavor of $n$-category.
    91 For each flavor of manifold there is a corresponding flavor of $n$-category.
    92 For simplicity, we will concentrate on the case of PL unoriented manifolds.
    92 For simplicity, we will concentrate on the case of PL unoriented manifolds.
       
    93 
       
    94 (An interesting open question is whether the techniques of this paper can be adapted to topological
       
    95 manifolds and plain, merely continuous homeomorphisms.
       
    96 The main obstacles are proving a version of Lemma \ref{basic_adaptation_lemma} and adapting the
       
    97 transversality arguments used in Lemma \ref{lem:colim-injective}.)
    93 
    98 
    94 An ambitious reader may want to keep in mind two other classes of balls.
    99 An ambitious reader may want to keep in mind two other classes of balls.
    95 The first is balls equipped with a map to some other space $Y$ (c.f. \cite{MR2079378}). 
   100 The first is balls equipped with a map to some other space $Y$ (c.f. \cite{MR2079378}). 
    96 This will be used below (see the end of \S \ref{ss:product-formula}) to describe the blob complex of a fiber bundle with
   101 This will be used below (see the end of \S \ref{ss:product-formula}) to describe the blob complex of a fiber bundle with
    97 base space $Y$.
   102 base space $Y$.
   658 We call the equivalence relation generated by collar maps and homeomorphisms
   663 We call the equivalence relation generated by collar maps and homeomorphisms
   659 isotopic (rel boundary) to the identity {\it extended isotopy}.
   664 isotopic (rel boundary) to the identity {\it extended isotopy}.
   660 
   665 
   661 The revised axiom is
   666 The revised axiom is
   662 
   667 
   663 %\addtocounter{axiom}{-1}
       
   664 \begin{axiom}[Extended isotopy invariance in dimension $n$]
   668 \begin{axiom}[Extended isotopy invariance in dimension $n$]
   665 \label{axiom:extended-isotopies}
   669 \label{axiom:extended-isotopies}
   666 Let $X$ be an $n$-ball, $b \in \cC(X)$, and $f: X\to X$ be a homeomorphism which 
   670 Let $X$ be an $n$-ball, $b \in \cC(X)$, and $f: X\to X$ be a homeomorphism which 
   667 acts trivially on the restriction $\bd b$ of $b$ to $\bd X$.
   671 acts trivially on the restriction $\bd b$ of $b$ to $\bd X$.
   668 Suppose furthermore that $f$ is isotopic to the identity through homeomorphisms which
   672 Suppose furthermore that $f$ is isotopic to the identity through homeomorphisms which
   673 
   677 
   674 \medskip
   678 \medskip
   675 
   679 
   676 We need one additional axiom.
   680 We need one additional axiom.
   677 It says, roughly, that given a $k$-ball $X$, $k<n$, and $c\in \cC(X)$, there exist sufficiently many splittings of $c$.
   681 It says, roughly, that given a $k$-ball $X$, $k<n$, and $c\in \cC(X)$, there exist sufficiently many splittings of $c$.
   678 We use this axiom in the proofs of \ref{lem:d-a-acyclic}, \ref{lem:colim-injective} \nn{...}.
   682 We use this axiom in the proofs of \ref{lem:d-a-acyclic} and \ref{lem:colim-injective}.
   679 All of the examples of (disk-like) $n$-categories we consider in this paper satisfy the axiom, but
   683 All of the examples of (disk-like) $n$-categories we consider in this paper satisfy the axiom, but
   680 nevertheless we feel that it is too strong.
   684 nevertheless we feel that it is too strong.
   681 In the future we would like to see this provisional version of the axiom replaced by something less restrictive.
   685 In the future we would like to see this provisional version of the axiom replaced by something less restrictive.
   682 
   686 
   683 We give two alternate versions of the axiom, one better suited for smooth examples, and one better suited to PL examples.
   687 We give two alternate versions of the axiom, one better suited for smooth examples, and one better suited to PL examples.