text/ncat.tex
changeset 415 8dedd2914d10
parent 411 98b8559b0b7a
child 416 c06a899bd1f0
equal deleted inserted replaced
414:214d944956e8 415:8dedd2914d10
     9 \subsection{Definition of $n$-categories}
     9 \subsection{Definition of $n$-categories}
    10 \label{ss:n-cat-def}
    10 \label{ss:n-cat-def}
    11 
    11 
    12 Before proceeding, we need more appropriate definitions of $n$-categories, 
    12 Before proceeding, we need more appropriate definitions of $n$-categories, 
    13 $A_\infty$ $n$-categories, modules for these, and tensor products of these modules.
    13 $A_\infty$ $n$-categories, modules for these, and tensor products of these modules.
    14 (As is the case throughout this paper, by ``$n$-category" we implicitly intend some notion of
    14 (As is the case throughout this paper, by ``$n$-category" we mean some notion of
    15 a `weak' $n$-category with `strong duality'.)
    15 a ``weak" $n$-category with ``strong duality".)
    16 
    16 
    17 The definitions presented below tie the categories more closely to the topology
    17 The definitions presented below tie the categories more closely to the topology
    18 and avoid combinatorial questions about, for example, the minimal sufficient
    18 and avoid combinatorial questions about, for example, the minimal sufficient
    19 collections of generalized associativity axioms; we prefer maximal sets of axioms to minimal sets.
    19 collections of generalized associativity axioms; we prefer maximal sets of axioms to minimal sets.
    20 For examples of topological origin, it is typically easy to show that they
    20 For examples of topological origin
       
    21 (e.g.\ categories whose morphisms are maps into spaces or decorated balls), 
       
    22 it is easy to show that they
    21 satisfy our axioms.
    23 satisfy our axioms.
    22 For examples of a more purely algebraic origin, one would typically need the combinatorial
    24 For examples of a more purely algebraic origin, one would typically need the combinatorial
    23 results that we have avoided here.
    25 results that we have avoided here.
    24 
    26 
    25 \medskip
    27 \medskip
    34 (This allows for strict associativity.)
    36 (This allows for strict associativity.)
    35 Still other definitions (see, for example, \cite{MR2094071})
    37 Still other definitions (see, for example, \cite{MR2094071})
    36 model the $k$-morphisms on more complicated combinatorial polyhedra.
    38 model the $k$-morphisms on more complicated combinatorial polyhedra.
    37 
    39 
    38 For our definition, we will allow our $k$-morphisms to have any shape, so long as it is homeomorphic to the standard $k$-ball.
    40 For our definition, we will allow our $k$-morphisms to have any shape, so long as it is homeomorphic to the standard $k$-ball.
    39 Thus we expect to associate a set of $k$-morphisms $\cC_k(X)$ to any $k$-manifold $X$ homeomorphic 
    41 Thus we associate a set of $k$-morphisms $\cC_k(X)$ to any $k$-manifold $X$ homeomorphic 
    40 to the standard $k$-ball.
    42 to the standard $k$-ball.
    41 By ``a $k$-ball" we mean any $k$-manifold which is homeomorphic to the 
    43 By ``a $k$-ball" we mean any $k$-manifold which is homeomorphic to the 
    42 standard $k$-ball.
    44 standard $k$-ball.
    43 We {\it do not} assume that it is equipped with a 
    45 We {\it do not} assume that it is equipped with a 
    44 preferred homeomorphism to the standard $k$-ball, and the same applies to ``a $k$-sphere" below.
    46 preferred homeomorphism to the standard $k$-ball, and the same applies to ``a $k$-sphere" below.
    56 \end{axiom}
    58 \end{axiom}
    57 
    59 
    58 
    60 
    59 (Note: We usually omit the subscript $k$.)
    61 (Note: We usually omit the subscript $k$.)
    60 
    62 
    61 We are so far  being deliberately vague about what flavor of $k$-balls
    63 We are being deliberately vague about what flavor of $k$-balls
    62 we are considering.
    64 we are considering.
    63 They could be unoriented or oriented or Spin or $\mbox{Pin}_\pm$.
    65 They could be unoriented or oriented or Spin or $\mbox{Pin}_\pm$.
    64 They could be topological or PL or smooth.
    66 They could be topological or PL or smooth.
    65 %\nn{need to check whether this makes much difference}
    67 %\nn{need to check whether this makes much difference}
    66 (If smooth, ``homeomorphism" should be read ``diffeomorphism", and we would need
    68 (If smooth, ``homeomorphism" should be read ``diffeomorphism", and we would need
    67 to be fussier about corners and boundaries.)
    69 to be fussier about corners and boundaries.)
    68 For each flavor of manifold there is a corresponding flavor of $n$-category.
    70 For each flavor of manifold there is a corresponding flavor of $n$-category.
    69 We will concentrate on the case of PL unoriented manifolds.
    71 For simplicity, we will concentrate on the case of PL unoriented manifolds.
    70 
    72 
    71 (The ambitious reader may want to keep in mind two other classes of balls.
    73 (The ambitious reader may want to keep in mind two other classes of balls.
    72 The first is balls equipped with a map to some other space $Y$ (c.f. \cite{MR2079378}). 
    74 The first is balls equipped with a map to some other space $Y$ (c.f. \cite{MR2079378}). 
    73 This will be used below to describe the blob complex of a fiber bundle with
    75 This will be used below to describe the blob complex of a fiber bundle with
    74 base space $Y$.
    76 base space $Y$.
    75 The second is balls equipped with a section of the the tangent bundle, or the frame
    77 The second is balls equipped with a section of the tangent bundle, or the frame
    76 bundle (i.e.\ framed balls), or more generally some flag bundle associated to the tangent bundle.
    78 bundle (i.e.\ framed balls), or more generally some flag bundle associated to the tangent bundle.
    77 These can be used to define categories with less than the ``strong" duality we assume here,
    79 These can be used to define categories with less than the ``strong" duality we assume here,
    78 though we will not develop that idea fully in this paper.)
    80 though we will not develop that idea fully in this paper.)
    79 
    81 
    80 Next we consider domains and ranges of morphisms (or, as we prefer to say, boundaries
    82 Next we consider domains and ranges of morphisms (or, as we prefer to say, boundaries
    92 boundary of a morphism.
    94 boundary of a morphism.
    93 Morphisms are modeled on balls, so their boundaries are modeled on spheres.
    95 Morphisms are modeled on balls, so their boundaries are modeled on spheres.
    94 In other words, we need to extend the functors $\cC_{k-1}$ from balls to spheres, for 
    96 In other words, we need to extend the functors $\cC_{k-1}$ from balls to spheres, for 
    95 $1\le k \le n$.
    97 $1\le k \le n$.
    96 At first it might seem that we need another axiom for this, but in fact once we have
    98 At first it might seem that we need another axiom for this, but in fact once we have
    97 all the axioms in the subsection for $0$ through $k-1$ we can use a colimit
    99 all the axioms in this subsection for $0$ through $k-1$ we can use a colimit
    98 construction, as described in Subsection \ref{ss:ncat-coend} below, to extend $\cC_{k-1}$
   100 construction, as described in Subsection \ref{ss:ncat-coend} below, to extend $\cC_{k-1}$
    99 to spheres (and any other manifolds):
   101 to spheres (and any other manifolds):
   100 
   102 
   101 \begin{lem}
   103 \begin{lem}
   102 \label{lem:spheres}
   104 \label{lem:spheres}
   105 homeomorphisms to the category of sets and bijections.
   107 homeomorphisms to the category of sets and bijections.
   106 \end{lem}
   108 \end{lem}
   107 
   109 
   108 We postpone the proof of this result until after we've actually given all the axioms.
   110 We postpone the proof of this result until after we've actually given all the axioms.
   109 Note that defining this functor for some $k$ only requires the data described in Axiom \ref{axiom:morphisms} at level $k$, 
   111 Note that defining this functor for some $k$ only requires the data described in Axiom \ref{axiom:morphisms} at level $k$, 
   110 along with the data described in the other Axioms at lower levels. 
   112 along with the data described in the other axioms at lower levels. 
   111 
   113 
   112 %In fact, the functors for spheres are entirely determined by the functors for balls and the subsequent axioms. (In particular, $\cC(S^k)$ is the colimit of $\cC$ applied to decompositions of $S^k$ into balls.) However, it is easiest to think of it as additional data at this point.
   114 %In fact, the functors for spheres are entirely determined by the functors for balls and the subsequent axioms. (In particular, $\cC(S^k)$ is the colimit of $\cC$ applied to decompositions of $S^k$ into balls.) However, it is easiest to think of it as additional data at this point.
   113 
   115 
   114 \begin{axiom}[Boundaries]\label{nca-boundary}
   116 \begin{axiom}[Boundaries]\label{nca-boundary}
   115 For each $k$-ball $X$, we have a map of sets $\bd: \cC_k(X)\to \cl{\cC}_{k-1}(\bd X)$.
   117 For each $k$-ball $X$, we have a map of sets $\bd: \cC_k(X)\to \cl{\cC}_{k-1}(\bd X)$.
   129 category structure.
   131 category structure.
   130 Note that this auxiliary structure is only in dimension $n$;
   132 Note that this auxiliary structure is only in dimension $n$;
   131 $\cC(Y; c)$ is just a plain set if $\dim(Y) < n$.
   133 $\cC(Y; c)$ is just a plain set if $\dim(Y) < n$.
   132 
   134 
   133 \medskip
   135 \medskip
   134 \nn{
   136 
   135 %At the moment I'm a little confused about orientations, and more specifically
   137 (In order to simplify the exposition we have concentrated on the case of 
   136 %about the role of orientation-reversing maps of boundaries when gluing oriented manifolds.
   138 unoriented PL manifolds and avoided the question of what exactly we mean by 
   137 Maybe need a discussion about what the boundary of a manifold with a 
   139 the boundary a manifold with extra structure, such as an oriented manifold.
   138 structure (e.g. orientation) means.
   140 In general, all manifolds of dimension less than $n$ should be equipped with the germ
   139 Tentatively, I think we need to redefine the oriented boundary of an oriented $n$-manifold.
   141 of a thickening to dimension $n$, and this germ should carry whatever structure we have 
   140 Instead of an ordinary oriented $(n-1)$-manifold via the inward (or outward) normal 
   142 on $n$-manifolds.
   141 first (or last) convention, perhaps it is better to define the boundary to be an $(n-1)$-manifold
   143 In addition, lower dimensional manifolds should be equipped with a framing
   142 equipped with an orientation of its once-stabilized tangent bundle.
   144 of their normal bundle in the thickening; the framing keeps track of which
   143 Similarly, in dimension $n-k$ we would have manifolds equipped with an orientation of 
   145 side (iterated) bounded manifolds lie on.
   144 their $k$ times stabilized tangent bundles.
   146 For example, the boundary of an oriented $n$-ball
   145 (cf. \cite{MR2079378}.)
   147 should be an $n{-}1$-sphere equipped with an orientation of its once stabilized tangent
   146 Probably should also have a framing of the stabilized dimensions in order to indicate which 
   148 bundle and a choice of direction in this bundle indicating
   147 side the bounded manifold is on.
   149 which side the $n$-ball lies on.)
   148 For the moment just stick with unoriented manifolds.}
   150 
   149 \medskip
   151 \medskip
   150 
   152 
   151 We have just argued that the boundary of a morphism has no preferred splitting into
   153 We have just argued that the boundary of a morphism has no preferred splitting into
   152 domain and range, but the converse meets with our approval.
   154 domain and range, but the converse meets with our approval.
   153 That is, given compatible domain and range, we should be able to combine them into
   155 That is, given compatible domain and range, we should be able to combine them into
   172 
   174 
   173 \begin{figure}[!ht]
   175 \begin{figure}[!ht]
   174 $$
   176 $$
   175 \begin{tikzpicture}[%every label/.style={green}
   177 \begin{tikzpicture}[%every label/.style={green}
   176 ]
   178 ]
   177 \node[fill=black, circle, label=below:$E$, inner sep=2pt](S) at (0,0) {};
   179 \node[fill=black, circle, label=below:$E$, inner sep=1.5pt](S) at (0,0) {};
   178 \node[fill=black, circle, label=above:$E$, inner sep=2pt](N) at (0,2) {};
   180 \node[fill=black, circle, label=above:$E$, inner sep=1.5pt](N) at (0,2) {};
   179 \draw (S) arc  (-90:90:1);
   181 \draw (S) arc  (-90:90:1);
   180 \draw (N) arc  (90:270:1);
   182 \draw (N) arc  (90:270:1);
   181 \node[left] at (-1,1) {$B_1$};
   183 \node[left] at (-1,1) {$B_1$};
   182 \node[right] at (1,1) {$B_2$};
   184 \node[right] at (1,1) {$B_2$};
   183 \end{tikzpicture}
   185 \end{tikzpicture}
   184 $$
   186 $$
   185 \caption{Combining two balls to get a full boundary.}\label{blah3}\end{figure}
   187 \caption{Combining two balls to get a full boundary.}\label{blah3}\end{figure}
   186 
   188 
   187 Note that we insist on injectivity above. \todo{Make sure we prove this, as a consequence of the next axiom, later.}
   189 Note that we insist on injectivity above. 
       
   190 The lemma follows from Definition \ref{def:colim-fields} and Lemma \ref{lem:colim-injective}.
   188 
   191 
   189 Let $\cl{\cC}(S)_E$ denote the image of $\gl_E$.
   192 Let $\cl{\cC}(S)_E$ denote the image of $\gl_E$.
   190 We will refer to elements of $\cl{\cC}(S)_E$ as ``splittable along $E$" or ``transverse to $E$". 
   193 We will refer to elements of $\cl{\cC}(S)_E$ as ``splittable along $E$" or ``transverse to $E$". 
   191 
   194 
   192 If $X$ is a $k$-ball and $E \sub \bd X$ splits $\bd X$ into two $k{-}1$-balls $B_1$ and $B_2$
   195 If $X$ is a $k$-ball and $E \sub \bd X$ splits $\bd X$ into two $k{-}1$-balls $B_1$ and $B_2$
   259 %Compositions of boundary and restriction maps will also be called restriction maps.
   262 %Compositions of boundary and restriction maps will also be called restriction maps.
   260 %For example, if $B$ is a $k$-ball and $Y\sub \bd B$ is a $k{-}1$-ball, there is a
   263 %For example, if $B$ is a $k$-ball and $Y\sub \bd B$ is a $k{-}1$-ball, there is a
   261 %restriction map from $\cC(B)_{\bd Y}$ to $\cC(Y)$.
   264 %restriction map from $\cC(B)_{\bd Y}$ to $\cC(Y)$.
   262 
   265 
   263 We will write $\cC(B)_Y$ for the image of $\gl_Y$ in $\cC(B)$.
   266 We will write $\cC(B)_Y$ for the image of $\gl_Y$ in $\cC(B)$.
   264 We will call elements of $\cC(B)_Y$ morphisms which are `splittable along $Y$' or `transverse to $Y$'.
   267 We will call elements of $\cC(B)_Y$ morphisms which are 
       
   268 ``splittable along $Y$'' or ``transverse to $Y$''.
   265 We have $\cC(B)_Y \sub \cC(B)_E \sub \cC(B)$.
   269 We have $\cC(B)_Y \sub \cC(B)_E \sub \cC(B)$.
   266 
   270 
   267 More generally, let $\alpha$ be a subdivision of a ball $X$ into smaller balls.
   271 More generally, let $\alpha$ be a subdivision of a ball $X$ into smaller balls.
   268 Let $\cC(X)_\alpha \sub \cC(X)$ denote the image of the iterated gluing maps from 
   272 Let $\cC(X)_\alpha \sub \cC(X)$ denote the image of the iterated gluing maps from 
   269 the smaller balls to $X$.
   273 the smaller balls to $X$.
   296 For each $k$-ball $X$ and $m$-ball $D$, with $k+m \le n$, there is a map $\cC(X)\to \cC(X\times D)$, 
   300 For each $k$-ball $X$ and $m$-ball $D$, with $k+m \le n$, there is a map $\cC(X)\to \cC(X\times D)$, 
   297 usually denoted $a\mapsto a\times D$ for $a\in \cC(X)$.
   301 usually denoted $a\mapsto a\times D$ for $a\in \cC(X)$.
   298 These maps must satisfy the following conditions.
   302 These maps must satisfy the following conditions.
   299 \begin{enumerate}
   303 \begin{enumerate}
   300 \item
   304 \item
   301 If $f:X\to X'$ and $\tilde{f}:X\times D \to X'\times D'$ are maps such that the diagram
   305 If $f:X\to X'$ and $\tilde{f}:X\times D \to X'\times D'$ are homeomorphisms such that the diagram
   302 \[ \xymatrix{
   306 \[ \xymatrix{
   303 	X\times D \ar[r]^{\tilde{f}} \ar[d]_{\pi} & X'\times D' \ar[d]^{\pi} \\
   307 	X\times D \ar[r]^{\tilde{f}} \ar[d]_{\pi} & X'\times D' \ar[d]^{\pi} \\
   304 	X \ar[r]^{f} & X'
   308 	X \ar[r]^{f} & X'
   305 } \]
   309 } \]
   306 commutes, then we have 
   310 commutes, then we have 
   361 \draw[->,red,line width=2pt] (-2.83,-1.5) -- (-2.83,-2.5);
   365 \draw[->,red,line width=2pt] (-2.83,-1.5) -- (-2.83,-2.5);
   362 \end{tikzpicture}
   366 \end{tikzpicture}
   363 $$
   367 $$
   364 \caption{Examples of pinched products}\label{pinched_prods}
   368 \caption{Examples of pinched products}\label{pinched_prods}
   365 \end{figure}
   369 \end{figure}
   366 (The need for a strengthened version will become apparent in appendix \ref{sec:comparing-defs}
   370 (The need for a strengthened version will become apparent in Appendix \ref{sec:comparing-defs}
   367 where we construct a traditional category from a topological category.)
   371 where we construct a traditional category from a topological category.)
   368 Define a {\it pinched product} to be a map
   372 Define a {\it pinched product} to be a map
   369 \[
   373 \[
   370 	\pi: E\to X
   374 	\pi: E\to X
   371 \]
   375 \]
   523 This axiom needs to be strengthened to force product morphisms to act as the identity.
   527 This axiom needs to be strengthened to force product morphisms to act as the identity.
   524 Let $X$ be an $n$-ball and $Y\sub\bd X$ be an $n{-}1$-ball.
   528 Let $X$ be an $n$-ball and $Y\sub\bd X$ be an $n{-}1$-ball.
   525 Let $J$ be a 1-ball (interval).
   529 Let $J$ be a 1-ball (interval).
   526 We have a collaring homeomorphism $s_{Y,J}: X\cup_Y (Y\times J) \to X$.
   530 We have a collaring homeomorphism $s_{Y,J}: X\cup_Y (Y\times J) \to X$.
   527 (Here we use the ``pinched" version of $Y\times J$.
   531 (Here we use the ``pinched" version of $Y\times J$.
   528 \nn{need notation for this})
   532 \nn{do we need notation for this?})
   529 We define a map
   533 We define a map
   530 \begin{eqnarray*}
   534 \begin{eqnarray*}
   531 	\psi_{Y,J}: \cC(X) &\to& \cC(X) \\
   535 	\psi_{Y,J}: \cC(X) &\to& \cC(X) \\
   532 	a & \mapsto & s_{Y,J}(a \cup ((a|_Y)\times J)) .
   536 	a & \mapsto & s_{Y,J}(a \cup ((a|_Y)\times J)) .
   533 \end{eqnarray*}
   537 \end{eqnarray*}
   575 \begin{equation*}
   579 \begin{equation*}
   576 \xymatrix@C+2cm{\cC(X) \ar[r]^(0.45){\text{glue}} & \cC(X \cup \text{collar}) \ar[r]^(0.55){\text{homeo}} & \cC(X)}
   580 \xymatrix@C+2cm{\cC(X) \ar[r]^(0.45){\text{glue}} & \cC(X \cup \text{collar}) \ar[r]^(0.55){\text{homeo}} & \cC(X)}
   577 \end{equation*}
   581 \end{equation*}
   578 
   582 
   579 \caption{Extended homeomorphism.}\label{glue-collar}\end{figure}
   583 \caption{Extended homeomorphism.}\label{glue-collar}\end{figure}
   580 We say that $\psi_{Y,J}$ is {\it extended isotopic} to the identity map.
   584 We call a map of this form a {\it collar map}.
   581 \nn{bad terminology; fix it later}
       
   582 \nn{also need to make clear that plain old isotopic to the identity implies
       
   583 extended isotopic}
       
   584 \nn{maybe remark that in some examples (e.g.\ ones based on sub cell complexes) 
       
   585 extended isotopies are also plain isotopies, so
       
   586 no extension necessary}
       
   587 It can be thought of as the action of the inverse of
   585 It can be thought of as the action of the inverse of
   588 a map which projects a collar neighborhood of $Y$ onto $Y$.
   586 a map which projects a collar neighborhood of $Y$ onto $Y$,
       
   587 or as the limit of homeomorphisms $X\to X$ which expand a very thin collar of $Y$
       
   588 to a larger collar.
       
   589 We call the equivalence relation generated by collar maps and homeomorphisms
       
   590 isotopic (rel boundary) to the identity {\it extended isotopy}.
   589 
   591 
   590 The revised axiom is
   592 The revised axiom is
   591 
   593 
   592 \addtocounter{axiom}{-1}
   594 \addtocounter{axiom}{-1}
   593 \begin{axiom}{\textup{\textbf{[topological  version]}} Extended isotopy invariance in dimension $n$}
   595 \begin{axiom}{\textup{\textbf{[topological  version]}} Extended isotopy invariance in dimension $n$.}
   594 \label{axiom:extended-isotopies}
   596 \label{axiom:extended-isotopies}
   595 Let $X$ be an $n$-ball and $f: X\to X$ be a homeomorphism which restricts
   597 Let $X$ be an $n$-ball and $f: X\to X$ be a homeomorphism which restricts
   596 to the identity on $\bd X$ and is extended isotopic (rel boundary) to the identity.
   598 to the identity on $\bd X$ and isotopic (rel boundary) to the identity.
   597 Then $f$ acts trivially on $\cC(X)$.
   599 Then $f$ acts trivially on $\cC(X)$.
       
   600 In addition, collar maps act trivially on $\cC(X)$.
   598 \end{axiom}
   601 \end{axiom}
   599 
       
   600 \nn{need to rephrase this, since extended isotopies don't correspond to homeomorphisms.}
       
   601 
   602 
   602 \smallskip
   603 \smallskip
   603 
   604 
   604 For $A_\infty$ $n$-categories, we replace
   605 For $A_\infty$ $n$-categories, we replace
   605 isotopy invariance with the requirement that families of homeomorphisms act.
   606 isotopy invariance with the requirement that families of homeomorphisms act.
   959 (i.e. fix an element of the colimit associated to $\bd W$).
   960 (i.e. fix an element of the colimit associated to $\bd W$).
   960 
   961 
   961 Finally, we construct $\cC(W)$ as the appropriate colimit of $\psi_{\cC;W}$.
   962 Finally, we construct $\cC(W)$ as the appropriate colimit of $\psi_{\cC;W}$.
   962 
   963 
   963 \begin{defn}[System of fields functor]
   964 \begin{defn}[System of fields functor]
       
   965 \label{def:colim-fields}
   964 If $\cC$ is an $n$-category enriched in sets or vector spaces, $\cl{\cC}(W)$ is the usual colimit of the functor $\psi_{\cC;W}$.
   966 If $\cC$ is an $n$-category enriched in sets or vector spaces, $\cl{\cC}(W)$ is the usual colimit of the functor $\psi_{\cC;W}$.
   965 That is, for each decomposition $x$ there is a map
   967 That is, for each decomposition $x$ there is a map
   966 $\psi_{\cC;W}(x)\to \cl{\cC}(W)$, these maps are compatible with the refinement maps
   968 $\psi_{\cC;W}(x)\to \cl{\cC}(W)$, these maps are compatible with the refinement maps
   967 above, and $\cl{\cC}(W)$ is universal with respect to these properties.
   969 above, and $\cl{\cC}(W)$ is universal with respect to these properties.
   968 \end{defn}
   970 \end{defn}
  1024 
  1026 
  1025 \todo{This next sentence is circular: these maps are an axiom, not a consequence of anything. -S} It is easy to see that
  1027 \todo{This next sentence is circular: these maps are an axiom, not a consequence of anything. -S} It is easy to see that
  1026 there are well-defined maps $\cC(W)\to\cC(\bd W)$, and that these maps
  1028 there are well-defined maps $\cC(W)\to\cC(\bd W)$, and that these maps
  1027 comprise a natural transformation of functors.
  1029 comprise a natural transformation of functors.
  1028 
  1030 
  1029 \todo{Explicitly say somewhere: `this proves Lemma \ref{lem:domain-and-range}'}
  1031 \begin{lem}
       
  1032 \label{lem:colim-injective}
       
  1033 Let $W$ be a manifold of dimension less than $n$.  Then for each
       
  1034 decomposition $x$ of $W$ the natural map $\psi_{\cC;W}(x)\to \cl{\cC}(W)$ is injective.
       
  1035 \end{lem}
       
  1036 \begin{proof}
       
  1037 \nn{...}
       
  1038 \end{proof}
  1030 
  1039 
  1031 \nn{need to finish explaining why we have a system of fields;
  1040 \nn{need to finish explaining why we have a system of fields;
  1032 need to say more about ``homological" fields? 
  1041 need to say more about ``homological" fields? 
  1033 (actions of homeomorphisms);
  1042 (actions of homeomorphisms);
  1034 define $k$-cat $\cC(\cdot\times W)$}
  1043 define $k$-cat $\cC(\cdot\times W)$}