# HG changeset patch # User Scott Morrison # Date 1275593627 25200 # Node ID eb03c4a92f98e20cf0aa416444b596cd757685c0 # Parent bc22926d4fb0d8ef0be877693e54a13c7e95c955 various changes, mostly rewriting intros to sections for exposition diff -r bc22926d4fb0 -r eb03c4a92f98 blob1.tex --- a/blob1.tex Thu Jun 03 09:47:18 2010 -0700 +++ b/blob1.tex Thu Jun 03 12:33:47 2010 -0700 @@ -36,7 +36,7 @@ to make more understandable \item[7] (S) do some work here -- identity morphisms are still imperfect. Say something about the cobordism and stabilization hypotheses \cite{MR1355899} in this setting? Say something about $E_n$ algebras? \item[7.6] is new! (S) read -\item[8] improve the beginning, (K) small blobs, finish proof for products, +\item[8] improve the beginning, finish proof for products, check the argument about maps \item[9] (K) proofs trail off \item[10] (S) read what's already here diff -r bc22926d4fb0 -r eb03c4a92f98 text/a_inf_blob.tex --- a/text/a_inf_blob.tex Thu Jun 03 09:47:18 2010 -0700 +++ b/text/a_inf_blob.tex Thu Jun 03 12:33:47 2010 -0700 @@ -221,6 +221,7 @@ \medskip +\todo{rephrase this} \begin{cor} \label{cor:new-old} The new-fangled and old-fashioned blob complexes are homotopic. diff -r bc22926d4fb0 -r eb03c4a92f98 text/ncat.tex --- a/text/ncat.tex Thu Jun 03 09:47:18 2010 -0700 +++ b/text/ncat.tex Thu Jun 03 12:33:47 2010 -0700 @@ -23,7 +23,7 @@ \medskip -There are many existing definitions of $n$-categories, with various intended uses. In any such definition, there are sets of $k$-morphisms for each $0 \leq k \leq n$. Generally, these sets are indexed by instances of a certain typical chape. +There are many existing definitions of $n$-categories, with various intended uses. In any such definition, there are sets of $k$-morphisms for each $0 \leq k \leq n$. Generally, these sets are indexed by instances of a certain typical shape. Some $n$-category definitions model $k$-morphisms on the standard bihedrons (interval, bigon, and so on). Other definitions have a separate set of 1-morphisms for each interval $[0,l] \sub \r$, a separate set of 2-morphisms for each rectangle $[0,l_1]\times [0,l_2] \sub \r^2$, @@ -32,27 +32,17 @@ Still other definitions (see, for example, \cite{MR2094071}) model the $k$-morphisms on more complicated combinatorial polyhedra. -For our definition, we will allow our $k$-morphisms to have any shape, so long as it is homeomorphic to the standard $k$-ball: - -\begin{axiom}[Morphisms]{\textup{\textbf{[preliminary]}}} -For any $k$-manifold $X$ homeomorphic -to the standard $k$-ball, we have a set of $k$-morphisms -$\cC_k(X)$. -\end{axiom} - -By ``a $k$-ball" we mean any $k$-manifold which is homeomorphic to the +For our definition, we will allow our $k$-morphisms to have any shape, so long as it is homeomorphic to the standard $k$-ball. Thus we expect to associate a set of $k$-morphisms $\cC_k(X)$ to any $k$-manifold $X$ homeomorphic +to the standard $k$-ball. By ``a $k$-ball" we mean any $k$-manifold which is homeomorphic to the standard $k$-ball. We {\it do not} assume that it is equipped with a preferred homeomorphism to the standard $k$-ball, and the same applies to ``a $k$-sphere" below. - Given a homeomorphism $f:X\to Y$ between $k$-balls (not necessarily fixed on the boundary), we want a corresponding bijection of sets $f:\cC(X)\to \cC(Y)$. -(This will imply ``strong duality", among other things.) -So we replace the above with +(This will imply ``strong duality", among other things.) Putting these together, we have -\addtocounter{axiom}{-1} \begin{axiom}[Morphisms] \label{axiom:morphisms} For each $0 \le k \le n$, we have a functor $\cC_k$ from @@ -107,7 +97,7 @@ homeomorphisms to the category of sets and bijections. \end{prop} -We postpone the proof of this result until after we've actually given all the axioms. Note that defining this functor for some $k$ only requires the data described in Axiom \ref{axiom:morphisms} at level $k$, along with the data described in the other Axioms at lower levels. +We postpone the proof \todo{} of this result until after we've actually given all the axioms. Note that defining this functor for some $k$ only requires the data described in Axiom \ref{axiom:morphisms} at level $k$, along with the data described in the other Axioms at lower levels. %In fact, the functors for spheres are entirely determined by the functors for balls and the subsequent axioms. (In particular, $\cC(S^k)$ is the colimit of $\cC$ applied to decompositions of $S^k$ into balls.) However, it is easiest to think of it as additional data at this point. @@ -479,26 +469,23 @@ \medskip -The alert reader will have already noticed that our definition of (plain) $n$-category -is extremely similar to our definition of topological fields. -The main difference is that for the $n$-category definition we restrict our attention to balls +The alert reader will have already noticed that our definition of a (plain) $n$-category +is extremely similar to our definition of a topological system of fields. +There are two essential differences. +First, for the $n$-category definition we restrict our attention to balls (and their boundaries), while for fields we consider all manifolds. -(A minor difference is that in the category definition we directly impose isotopy -invariance in dimension $n$, while in the fields definition we have non-isotopy-invariant fields -but then mod out by local relations which imply isotopy invariance.) -Thus a system of fields determines an $n$-category simply by restricting our attention to -balls. +Second, in category definition we directly impose isotopy +invariance in dimension $n$, while in the fields definition we have do not expect isotopy invariance on fields +but instead remember a subspace of local relations which contain differences of isotopic fields. (Recall that the compensation for this complication is that we can demand that the gluing map for fields is injective.) +Thus a system of fields and local relations $(\cF,\cU)$ determines an $n$-category $\cC_ {\cF,\cU}$ simply by restricting our attention to +balls and, at level $n$, quotienting out by the local relations: +\begin{align*} +\cC_{\cF,\cU}(B^k) & = \begin{cases}\cF(B) & \text{when $k